Wittgenstein
Ludwig Wittgenstein is particularly interesting because in Philosophical Investigations (PI) he repudiated all of his earlier work in logical positivism and the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (TLP), along with much of what was traditionally thought of as philosophy, and took a radically new track in the last twenty years of his life. Young Wittgenstein was more certain that he had solved all major philosophical problems, while the older Wittgenstein had completely lost all such certainties. There were even hints in his earlier work of this later, more explicit existential despair, pessimism and even cynicism about the limits of philosophy, which certainly became more profound over the years. He was no longer able to view the world as consisting of facts that were logical representations of objects that really existed or at least had the potential to exist. Thoughts and ideas formed pictures that were models of reality, while everything outside of this was nonsense (TLP, 1922, 1961, p. 2.12). Even at an early age, Wittgenstein thought that most of the theories of philosophy, metaphysics, aesthetics, epistemology and even his own work were nonsensical -- literally senseless -- and could not be proven or even represented (TLP p. 4.003). Over time they might possibly be corrected by logical analysis, although the older Wittgenstein no longer believed this. Wittgenstein could therefore be interpreted as a nihilist who had given up the traditional philosophical quest for truth, meaning or universal principles, and he has often been described in these terms. This was not the case with Gilbert Ryle and his other major disciples in the decades after his death, he asserted that his major contribution had been to separate philosophy from science, as well as metaphysics or meaningless generalizations and speculations that were not firmly grounded in reality.
Wittgenstein openly denounced his earlier work as too dogmatic, and moved away from logic into theories about language games, which culminated in Philosophical Investigations, published posthumously in 1953. He had come to oppose traditional ideas about logic, truth, thought and philosophy as a whole, and he denied that "individual words in language name objects" (PI, 1953, 2009, p. 1). Words had no meaning most of the time except for how they were used in a particular context, and did not refer to exterior objects or internal mental processes. They could be used for a wide variety of purposes and the task of the philosopher was to describe these without making profound generalizations (PI, p. 66). Language games could take an almost infinite number of forms, which made it difficult to define the concept at all, but ranging from telling jokes to acting to engaging in theoretical speculation. Wittgenstein rejected all general explanations in this early form of postmodernism and discourse analysis, but insisted on examining the actual use of words through "a complicated network of similarities, overlapping and crisscrossing" (PI, p. 66).
All language games had rules, and these were socially and historically constructed rather than ideals or absolutes in the Platonic sense. Once again, the main questions were how the rules were learned, enforced, altered or ignored in actual practice. They were also made to be broken so that "if everything can be made out to accord with the rule, then it can also be made out to conflict with it. And so there would be neither accord nor conflict" (PI 201). At times, Wittgenstein seemed to be skeptical that any facts existed at all about how such rules might be used. In addition, all individuals had their own private-language games which were meaningful only to them and followed their own rules. These did not follow the publicly-accepted forms of language and referred only to "what can only be known to the person speaking; to his immediate private sensations" (PI 243). Public languages all had their own grammars, which were not simply rigid rules found in textbooks but described objects and ideas in mutually comprehensible ways. Human life could not exist at all without these shared understandings about grammar in the broadest sense.
In the end, Wittgenstein denied that philosophers should have any real theories or explanations, and regarded philosophy more as a form of therapy. No single, universally valid method or system existed but "there are indeed methods, like different therapies" (PI, p. 133). Philosophy had to be humble and admit that it did not really know the answers to the ultimate questions, and could only offer hints and suggestions to how they might be solved. Most of its previous theories were meaningless verbiage, more language games that could be deconstructed, as postmodernists would use the term. Metaphysical speculations were particularly meaningless and philosophers would do better to say nothing at all than indulge...
".. other living species,... also with the total environment in which we live." They explain the human ecosystem to include three fundamental organizing conceptions: the human environed unit (HEU); the natural environment (NE); the human constructed environment (HCE). The following diagram portrays "The Human Ecosystem": Bubolz, Eicher, and Sontag (1979, p. 29) The human environed unit (HEU) displayed in the center is located in a specific space in time and can be a
EBP Project: Will Every Two Hour Turning and Positioning Decrease Pressure Ulcers in the Eldery Bed Bound Population in Nursing Homes? Practicum: Clinical rotations with preceptor; serving patients with acute, chronic and new medical issues. One of the things I have discovered during my recent experiences with both academic and clinical education and an EBP project is that there are numerous and effective ways of learning, presenting, and communicating. Each method, however,
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now