¶ … Lecturer:
I have two observations- one small but interesting and one for which I would like a response.
The first- you have transposed the authors names as Ingram and Schneider- in deed this is small but important - you will want to cite them as Schneider and Ingram going forward- as I said - small but important
Next I think you can develop your response to item 3 regarding your research interest.(my research interest is African-American women in the gas and oil field and how minority set aside programs fail them)
You have made a few claims that public policy is weak and that public policy fails- What is the weakness you have identified? How are you understanding failure? What kind of policies are you including in these statements and what is the connection to your research? I ask that you spend a bit more time on this section and submit a revision or addendum no later than April 7th.
Breath and think and write a bit more - you already know what you want to say- take this time to say it as clearly as you typically do
Critically Assessing the Debates and Critiques of Rationality and Public Policy
In spite of facing great disapproval, the theory of rational choice has attained exceptional importance among the general theories that account for human action. Its importance ranges across the whole continuum of social scientific subdomains (Chai, 2001). Similar to economists, proponents of the theory of rational choice maintain the premise that humanity is rational, and that it has preferences regarding outcomes. Successively, a person opts for preferable options above those that are less preferable. Furthermore, proponents of this theory typically assume such preferences stem from and simply reflect the self-interests of different individuals (Hampsher-Monk & Hindmoor, 2009). Normally, at the foundation of the theory of rational choice is a consideration of at least one discrete decision-making entity's choice behavior. Rational choice theoreticians usually assume the entity above is characteristic of (i.e., represents) a bigger group. After the establishment of individual behavior, the analysis commonly progresses to determine the interaction of individual choices for generating results (Green, 2002).
Espeland (2000) believes rational decision theories are formulated by a single group of an agency with the aim of resolving a couple of pressing issues: offering a structure to facilitate broad and effective individual participation in decisions impacting them, and coming up with a way to integrate incongruent facts. Decision-making under rational choice necessitates integration of diverse elements of value, via a succession of tradeoffs, into one common measure (e.g., utility or price) (Espeland, 2001). Typically, rational choice examinations commence on the basis that an individual agent or some agents maximize utility (in other words, selecting the preferable option). The existence of limitations is a second key facet of this choice process. Limitations necessitate making choices. An advantage of the theory is its clear tradeoffs between alternatives.
Through knowledge and tools of rational decision-making, a transformation has been witnessed in when, how, and which individuals could take part in bureaucratic decision-making. One means this was accomplished by making people a key extrajudicial instrument to diffuse the administrative "interest group" theory. Citizens' aforementioned expanded scope of participation in agency decisions is an extension of democratic practices apparently challenging entities that place emphasis on the irresoluble strains between democratic and bureaucratic governance. Nevertheless, despite a greater number of individuals taking part in decisions, terms of involvement continued to be stringently regulated by technical agency experts as well as the notions of rationality informing agency models. In the case of certain groups, decision-making access was limited by a kind of stringent instrumental rationality considered to be misrepresenting their decision-making interests (Espeland, 2000).
Meanwhile, Elinor Ostrom's take on the theory of rational choice involves a criticism of a few suppositions posited by it. One critiqued postulation is that of zero contribution: this theory claims self-regarding conduct is required even when cooperating assures remunerations exceeding non-cooperative options in value. Some exceptions are instances of disproportionately high private utility, with a single player or a tiny special cluster having the inducement to deliver public goods. However, frequently, independent contribution to providing a public good is improbable, because sensible, self-interested people won't take steps to accomplish group (i.e., shared) interests. The idea that people are unable to rise above issues about joint action, and require externally imposed directions for accomplishing personal long-run self-interests, is the structure logically and painstakingly picked apart by Ostrom in the former half of her article. Largely utilizing lab evidence of the theory of rational choice, within scenarios of joint action (Auer, 2014).
In Ostrom's article, an attempt has been made to prove the human personality's flexibility about equity considerations and joint decision-making. But results which prove good...
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now