Verified Document

Platos Argument: Art Is An Imitation Of An Imitation Essay

Abstract
Plato’s concepts of art and aesthetics encompass the core elements of his philosophical principles. Specifically, Plato shows how art becomes an imitation of an imitation: a clear reference to the philosopher’s concept of forms. Within Plato’s philosophy of art being nothing more than an imitation of an imitation is a value judgment, because Plato proposes that anything that is an imitation is also something that distracts and distorts reality. In other words, art can adversely impact the human ability to use reason. However, art served a fundamentally different purpose in ancient Greece than it does in the twenty-first century. Plato’s philosophy of art and aesthetics can seem anachronistic in light of the role art plays in postmodern society. When viewed in light of the role art played in ancient Greece, though, Plato’s philosophy of art showcases the logic behind the allegory of the cave in the Republic. Essentially, art can be little more than an imitation of an imitation when it remains derivative and unconscious of the political import of human creative acts.

Introduction

Every person has at some point viewed art that is little more than an imitation: works that depict scenes from daily life, portraits, still life scenes, or landscapes. Even when art becomes imbued with emotional intensity or is executed well, elevating the senses to appreciation, awe and wonder, it is still little more than entertainment. Plato considered art in this way: as something frivolous at best and at worst, even dangerous due to its ability to distract the mind from what is true and real (“Plato,” n.d.). According to Plato, then, beauty can only be located in the truth. Art can lead the person to contemplate and appreciate aesthetic beauty, but can never lead the person to truth. 

Furthermore, art is defined by its being created by human beings. Human beings already have a distorted sense of reality. In Plato’s Republic, the philosopher relays his concept of the Forms. Using the allegory of the cave, Plato shows how the majority of what the human mind perceives is a distortion of reality. The allegory showcases a group of people in a cave who become fascinated by the shadows dancing on the wall instead of venturing outside the cave to discover the source of the shadows: the sun and the light that refracts off of physical objects. A person who does leave the cave to perceive the truth may be ostracized from society, but at least that person possesses great power in knowing the truth about reality. 

Using this same analogy of the cave and the shadows created by the sun, art would be like cave drawings. Plato wants his audience to understand that art is an imitation of an imitation. Like the child’s game of telephone, the root message becomes distorted when it is filtered through successive layers of consciousness. Plato believes in the existence of an absolute truth that is independent of the human mind, and suggests that the human mind mistakes illusion for reality. Becoming overly wrapped up in aesthetics can lead a mind astray from the core goal of philosophy: which is to discern the truth.

For Plato, the job of the philosopher is to venture outside of the cave. Venturing outside of the cave means sacrificing the shared reality of the shadows on the wall in favor of knowing the truth. Therefore, Plato assumes an antagonistic role towards art. Anything that comes in the way of the truth is akin to lying, which makes it unethical. In Plato’s worldview, art can therefore be seen as unethical given that it is an imitation of an imitation.  Plato disregards other aspects of artistic expression such as the inherent value of art, art for art’s sake, or the sheer pleasure that art can provide to the artist and the audience. 

Yet there is no evidence that conceptual art existed at all in Plato’s time. If all art is merely imitative, then surely it could be argued that it leads the mind away from more intellectually fruitful activities like seeking the truth. Plato had not begun to...…their rituals and folkways should not become rigid. Rituals and art, however beautiful, are no substitute for truth, ethics, and justice.

In fact, art often serves to bolster the power of religion or politics. Even in ancient Greece, long before the emergence of the Catholic Church and other globally influential organizations commissioned grandiose works of art to propagate their dogma, art was used for the solidification and perpetuation of power. The temples of ancient Greece are in fact part of the aesthetic body Plato refers to when the philosopher critiques art as a poor imitation of the truth. The masses mistake the beauty of the temple for the reality of the cosmos. Similarly, the masses mistake the dogma of their religion for the power of human reason. Socrates speaks in favor of reason over religion and is killed for it in the Apology. Plato also decries the way art can be used to distract and numb the public, which allows the public to be easily manipulated.

It is not so much that Plato is against art or undervalues aesthetics in any way. On the contrary, Plato does acknowledge the importance of beauty as a Form (Pappas, 2016). Even the most splendid work of art is still but an imitation of what the artist truly wants to say, much in the same way language never fully conveys the deepest sentiments of the speaker. Human beings should always strive to understand more and to seek the truth rather than remain satisfied with amusing shadows on the wall.

Conclusion

Plato provides a consistent and controversial theory of art. Art is an imitation of an imitation, according to the Greek philosopher. Most of what human beings think they know ends up being but a shadow of the real truth. The unfolding of scientific knowledge and inquiry has dispelled countless illusions, just as the philosopher exposes the shadows on the wall for what they really are. While art can lead a person to contemplate and seek the truth, it can never actually be ultimate reality.

References

Brook,…

Sources used in this document:

References

Brook, E. (2008). Art imitating art. https://contempaesthetics.org/newvolume/pages/article.php?articleID=516

Pappas, N. (2016). Plato’s aesthetics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-aesthetics/

Plato. Apology. Translated by B. Jowett. Retrieved from: http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/apology.html

Plato. Republic. Translated by T. Sheehan. Retrieved from: https://web.stanford.edu/class/ihum40/cave.pdf

“Plato,” (n.d.). Retrieved from: http://users.rowan.edu/~clowney/Aesthetics/philos_artists_onart/plato.htm


Cite this Document:
Copy Bibliography Citation

Related Documents

Platos Argument: Art is an Imitation of an Imitation
Words: 2141 Length: 7 Document Type: Essay

Abstract  Like most western philosophers, Plato focused a substantial amount of energy on aesthetics.  Aesthetics is the philosophical inquiry into beauty.  For many philosophers, the concept of beauty was synonymous with the concept of art.  However, Plato made a substantial distinction between beauty and art.  Not only did he consider art a poor imitation of beauty, in fact labeling it an imitation of an imitation, but he thought that this imitation

Plato What Is the Problem
Words: 795 Length: 2 Document Type: Term Paper

Using the ring of Gyges as his 'proof,' he finds the last reason to be the most persuasive. What Socrates definition of justice in the state is as found in Book IV? Compare the parts of the just state to the parts of the just soul. Describe the virtues of each. Socrates defines justice in terms of balance, as every person doing what he is best suited to do -- to

Innovation in Business Is It an Art or Science
Words: 664 Length: 2 Document Type: Essay

Innovation Is an Art Innovation in business, is it an Art or Science? Innovation is an art, not a science To answer the question of whether innovation is an art or science, it first must be determined what is art and what is science. In terms of 'art,' the image that immediately comes to mind is Michelangelo's David. The great Renaissance artist said that he felt he liberated the sculpture from the marble,

Literature Theory
Words: 2025 Length: 6 Document Type: Term Paper

Plato, Marx, And Critical Thought David Richter's book is absolutely indispensable, as it is one of the few anthologies willing to acknowledge the existence of and include well-chosen examples from the long history of critical thought and how it helps us understand what we read, why we read, and what we value. The greatest strength of Richter's work is that it simply starts at the beginning of classical literature and moves forward

Vagina Monologues
Words: 1298 Length: 4 Document Type: Term Paper

Vagina Monologues: A Response Theatrical performances of any kind are uniquely poised to evoke a myriad of audience responses. Unlike many other forms of artistic expression, theatre involves the visual, auditory, and emotional -- in short, a wide range of the human aesthetic experience is evoked in the performance. Thus, especially when the subject matter is of a particular novelty or controversial nature, one can virtually count on a strong aesthetic

Philosophy Opposing Philosophical Views Philosophy
Words: 1199 Length: 4 Document Type: Research Proposal

Jacques Derrida has been accused of writing in a deliberately obtuse and obfuscated manner, so the relationship between his work and that of Plato's might not be immediately discernible. Perhaps the clearest connection between the two can be derived from Derrida's of Grammatology, especially as it compares to Plato's aesthetics and view of reality. In this rather dense treatise, Derrida first outlines the phenomenon of what he calls logocentrism --

Sign Up for Unlimited Study Help

Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.

Get Started Now