Philosophy
In Book I of Plato's Republic, Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus provide intellectual foils for Socrates's ethical philosophy. Socrates responds to Thrasymachus's stance, which is essentially that, "the life of an unjust person is better than that of a just one," (p 88; 347e). Thrasymachus goes so far as to state that justice is "noble naivete," and therefore not worth pursuing at all (348c). Glaucon immediately takes the side of Thrasymachus, by stating that the life of an unjust person is "more profitable," at the very least, than the just life (p. 88, 347e). Agreeing with Glaucon's doctrine of self-interest, Adeimantus offers his two bits in Book II of The Republic. Glaucon's brand of justice is that good reputation is the most important thing. A person does not want to be just if those just acts go unnoticed or unrecognized. More importantly, Adeimantus states that a person would be better off committing unjust acts and getting away with them because their reputation would remain intact. Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus each offer sensible, practical, and material counter claims to Plato's (Socrates's) central thesis that Justice is an end in itself and a goal that also brings about Goodness and Happiness. Plato meets the intellectual challenge of Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus in two ways: referring to the concept of the Forms; and referring to the concept of the tripartite division of the soul. The tripartite division of the soul has its macrocosmic counterpart in the polis, and therefore an orderly soul is matched by an orderly society. When Aristotle grapples with the validity and value of both Virtue and Justice, he takes a different approach than Plato does. Aristotle cuts to the heart of the argument by insisting on a distinction between acts that are just and acts that are virtuous. Moreover, Aristotle's ordering of the soul is less rigid than Plato's. Aristotle's argument is more effective for responding to Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus not because he proves his case better, but because he appeals to the logical and ethical framework that Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus work with; whereas Plato does not do that.
Plato is, in modern terms, not on the same wavelength as Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus. Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus are coming basically from a utilitarian perspective in which there are no moral absolutes. With no absolute ethical truth or values, the ends can easily justify the means. It makes sense, then, that Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus do not find inherent value or worth in either justice or virtue. For Plato, Justice and Virtue are Forms. They are inherently and immutable absolute states that must be achieved and attained in order for a human being to experience happiness. Happiness is an end-product, symptom, or a by-product of Justice.
Plato's vision of an orderly universe with the Forms as the absolute and Right expression of all things runs contrary to the metaphysical vision that Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus posit, even though their metaphysic is more immature than that of Socrates/Plato. With regards to the argument over the validity of Justice, Thrasymachus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus simply point to practical matters that Plato finds too mundane to entertain. For example, Thrasymachus points out the value of the self-serving existence; he argues that a self-serving type act can be unjust but that type of injustice is ethically permissible because it preempts injustice done to the self. Thrasymachus is actually completely unconcerned with justice, as he presents ethics as "what's in it for me?" All Plato can say in response is that the abstract notion of Justice is Good and it has inherent value.
Plato's abstract thinking is less effective than Aristotle's long-winded logical debate because the latter provides room for Thrasymachus's mindset. Socrates's commitment to Justice as an abstract Goal has no bearing on Thrasymachus's worldview. Thrasymachus's worldview remains stalwartly materialistic and selfish. If he were in the room, Aristotle would have observed that Thrasymachus is simply enacting the Doctrine of the Mean in his method of calculated thinking. If Justice and Virtue have no clear ends that serve the self, then they have no clear value for the likes of Thrasymachus. Thrasymachus is a political realist. He sees that justice is not an abstract ideal; or even if it were, its ideal would be untenable for human beings. Thrasymachus finds that those in positions of power who wield the sword of justice are the only ones empowered to determine what acts are deemed just, and what acts are deemed unjust. For an...
This is Aristotle's launching pad for his discussion of politics. To him, ethics and politics are matters of rational judgment, stemming from the natural inclinations of individual humans. This notion is reflected in Aristotle's analysis of the constitutional doctrines of some 158 cities. Essentially, he recognized that every state -- necessarily city states -- exist in unique sets of circumstances that act upon the universal forms of ethics in ways
Aristotle & Metaphysics Aristotle calls the science he is seeking 'first philosophy or theology'. The objective of this study is to answer the question of what does first philosophy or theology consist and what is its object. In addition, this study will ask in what ways that it differs from other sciences and in what sense is it first? In the final analysis this study will answer if Aristotle's 'first philosophy
Aristotle thought happiness was longer in coming, it was the manner of being actualized and fulfilling one's true potential using their own individual gifts: Again, if the virtues are concerned with actions and passions, and every passion and every action is accompanied by pleasure and pain, for this reason also virtue will be concerned with pleasures and pains. This is indicated also by the fact that punishment is indicated by
Plato & Aristotle The Platonic theory of knowledge is divided into two parts: a quest first to discover whether there are any unchanging objects and to identify and describe them and second to illustrate how they could be known by the use of reason, that is, via the dialectical method. Plato used various literary devices for illustrating his theory; the most famous of these is the allegory of the cave in
Certainly, rhetoric lends itself to the discovery of truth, as truth (Aristotle suggests) always makes more intuitive and intellectual sense compared to falsehood, and so equally talented rhetoricians will be more convincing sharing the truth than sharing falsehood. However, critics have pointed out that there is so "tension between Aristotle's epistemological optimism and his attempt to come to terms with rhetoric as a culturally and contextually specific social institution....
Socrates asked them to come forward with their thoughts if they were "still doubtful about the argument." The two proceed to make a sophisticated argument, contrary to Socrates' points, that were counterexamples to the points about the body and the soul that Socrates had been making with such eloquence. It was cross-examination, but it was also a series of new hypotheses that Cebes and Simmias presented to the philosopher
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now