Hume's Problem Of Induction
David Hume is known as one of the foremost skeptics and humanists of his time, who exalted in mankind's ability to transform the world through science. Somewhat ironically, then, one of his most far-reaching philosophical contributions was to phrase the problem of induction which today is often thought to deny scientific knowledge. Just a couple chapters of a single book, Hume posed a question which has yet to be satisfactorily answered, despite the great intervening time. In its most simple form, Hume's problem merely asked what evidence there was to support the instinctive understanding that the future would resemble the past, and then pointed out that since he could see no logical reason why this should be the case, then he could not with reasonably say that it must be so. And despite attempts to dismiss his challenge, it seems no one has yet come up with a simple logical response. So the challenge to find some straightforward reason to trust our instinctual inductions still stands, and though a number of alternatives have been posed, none stand up to theoretical perusal. If it is possible to argue from experience (which is to say, to use induction) to get at empirical truth, this seems to be more a coincidence than a rationally determined outcome -- for according to purely logical thought, there is no indisputable evidence that the future will resemble the past or that observed instances can predict new instances.
Before going any farther into the indefensibility of induction, it would be well worth while to take a moment to explain the difference between deduction and induction. Deduction is understood to be the method by which knowledge of specificities is gleaned from knowledge of generalities. It is based entirely on internal reasoning and thought, and does not depend on the existence of an external world to validate its conclusions. So long as its premises are true, and the steps in logic are legitimate, its conclusions will follow per force. Inductive reasoning, on the other hand, is understood to be the method by which (perceived) knowledge of general rules and principles can be gleaned from surveying specific cases and examples. It depends on the assumption that some causal link can be found between what has occurred and been observed, and depends on external evidence for its conclusions.
For some reason, the traditional example of how inductive reasoning works is to ask how it can be known that the sun will rise tomorrow. It is certain that every day as far back as one can remember or research, the sun has risen every day. How does this prove, however, that it will rise tomorrow? Even barring a super nova or an asteroid hit that took Earth off its axis, how could we know that the so-called laws of physics will be still active tomorrow? Mere deduction cannot prove that the sun will rise, though it may be able to explain how it rises. One depends rather on past experience to predict the future. The sun will rise, we believe, because it has always risen in the past.
However charming this example may be, it seems slightly misleading in its implications. The sun has risen 100% of the time from now back to the beginning of recorded history, and so it seems a very good inductive bet. However, inductive reasoning can also apply to categories where there is merely a high percentage of correlation. For example, one might reason inductively that a certain car is able to go approximately a specific maximum speed under equal conditions, even though that speed may vary slightly from test to test. Induction deals both with events that repeat without fail, and with probabilities.
The problem which Hume proposes for inductive reasoning is that while it seems like commonsense to trust it (and he never indicates that one should not live one's life according to the common sense of induction), there is no philosophic or logical reason to think it is trustworthy. A chicken who has been fed every morning by the same farmer and so inductively comes to expect food and kindness from that feeding hand may in fact be exercising common and even reasonable sense, but she is not actually being logical -- as she will discover on the day that the farmer kills her for dinner instead of feeding her. In the same way, perhaps,...
This is the problem of induction in a nutshell, and it is something that has alternatively been seen as one of the most severe limitations on true knowledge about the world or as a non-issue in any practical terms. If inductive reasoning cannot be trusted, then all past experience and even experimental data is essentially meaningless in predicting the future and there is no logical reason to assume things should
However saying that'd knows P. But doesn't believe it to be true under all conditions and in all time periods would be a more appropriate and rational way of putting it. We must mention here the principle of Induction which states that: "Unobserved cases and merely possible cases are likely to resemble observed cases" (Bonjour: 57). However when a person refuses to accept this, he is refuting inductive claims.
Hume's Argument Against Induction According to the empiricist English philosopher David Hume, inductive logic is inherently invalid. Hume took an extremely radical view of empiricism, the point of philosophical view that immediate, perceptual experience alone should validate inquiry into the nature of human existence and the nature of reality. Inductive logic is derived from assumptions and hypothesis about natural laws that govern the universe. Because every situation is different, Hume believed,
Jean-Francois Lyotard (the Postmodern condition: A Knowledge Report 1979) describes postmodernism in the context of nature of social bond. He argues that due to the advent of the technology and with the invention of computer, information has been more restricted in the form of procedures and program. According to him some one must have access to all the information to check whether the decisions are madder correctly. He discuss in
Philosophy Nietzsche often identified life itself with "will to power," that is, with an instinct for growth and durability. This concept provides yet another way of interpreting the ascetic ideal, since it is Nietzsche's contention "that all the supreme values of mankind lack this will -- that values which are symptomatic of decline, nihilistic values, are lording it under the holiest names" (Kaufmann 1959). Thus, traditional philosophy, religion, and morality
Karl Popper is arguably one of the greatest philosophers of the twentieth century because of his role as one of the pioneers of philosophy of science. Popper was a political and social philosopher of significant stature, a dedicated campaigner and strong defender of the Open Society, and a committed rival of all types of conventionalism, skepticism and relativism in human affairs and science (Thorton, n.d.). He considered one of the
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now