Foot: Moral Beliefs
L. Jones
Philippa Foot's Moral Beliefs
The concept of moral relativism is extremely troubling for many. Indeed, the human animal is desperately in need of a certain "moral order," or an intense longing to have life's issues, events and decisions neatly classified into realms of "good" and "bad," "right" and wrong. However, as most individuals blessed with a life that stretches into adulthood know all too well, other's conceptions of good and bad actions often differ greatly from one's own -- and, even more puzzling, those "others" seem to genuinely believe in their own conception of reality just as much an individual how holds the completly opposite view. In her work Moral Beliefs, Philippa Foot gives her take on this issue; namely in her response to the viability of systems of belief that allow moral eccentrism (the foundation on which moral relativism is built), and her belief in the untenability of the non-cognitivist position.
From the beginning of her work, Philippa Foot sets out to "look critically at the premises" on which many people reject naturalism -- that values of morality or goodness arise out of the human's inherent understanding of reality, quite apart from special circumstances. In short, it is a philosophy that is the opposite of moral relativism. It is a system on which any individual is equally bound by its moral principles, regardless of evidential facts She writes:
..the whole of moral philosophy, as it is now widely taught, rests on a contrast between statementst of fact and evaluations, which runs something like this: 'The truth or falsity of statements of fact is shown by means of evidence; and what counts as evidence is laid down in the meaning of the expressions occurring in the statement of fact. (83)
The difference, according to Foot, between these evidential principles of fact, and evaluations is significant. She notes that, "...no two people can make the same statement and count completely different things as evidence; in the end one at least of them could be convicted of linguistic ignorance."(83) Further, unlike in the relativist scheme of things, "..."if a man is given good evidence for a factual conclusion he cannot just refute to accept the conclusion on the ground that in his scheme of things this evidence is not evidence at all."(83) To allow oneself to delve into an evaluation of the evidence is to possibly fall into the realm of "moral eccentrism," the unacceptable spawn of non-cognitivism. Again, she writes:
An evaluation is not connected logically with the factual statements on which it is based. One may say that a thing is good because of some fact about I, and another may refuse to take that fact as any evidence at all, for nothing is laid down in the meaning of 'good' which connects it with one piece of 'evidence' rather than another. It follows that a moral eccentric could argue to moral conclusions from quite idiosyncratic premises... (84)
If, for example, one is allowed to accept a non-naturalist point-of-view, then, not only does one run the risk of sinking into abject relativism (the ultimate free-for-all of society). For, not only can an individual who accepts this kind of thinking base his or her moral beliefs on assumptions that only he or she recognize as valid. Further, he or she could also refuse to agree with someone else's evaluation because the assumptions or standards of evaluation are not ones that he or she accepts.
However, according to Foot, this kind of non-naturalism or non-cognitivism is in error, illustrated by the notion that the proper use of words demonstrates their ability to communicate clear evaluations of moral significance and meaning. In specific, Foot illustrates this point in her discussion of the words "proud" and "dangerous."
In specific, Foot explains, in the case of "pride":
Given any description of an object, action, personal characteristic,...
Philippa Foot Thought Experiment 1 J.S. Mill would tell the rescuer in Rescue I to save the five as that would promote the greatest common good. In Rescue II, it is not as easy to say the same thing—for while it is obviously better to save five than it is to save one, intentionally killing one to save five does not come with the same moral assurances as simply choosing to save
active and passive euthanasia. Why does James Rachels think there is no moral difference between them? Active euthanasia is the "mercy killing" of a life to prevent further suffering; passive euthanasia is deliberately allowing that life to die of "natural" causes. James Rachels believes there is no moral difference between active and passive euthanasia for a few reasons. First, in many cases where passive euthanasia is allowed (meaning it has
This can ultimately become the justification for refusal to euthanize a person even if they have given their permission. While the rights of the individual must be respected, even if they wish to die, others cannot, must not, accede to the individuals' wishes if they do not agree with it. The underlying basis of euthanasia must be the ending of a life who's continuance is generally accepted as an
Female Body Women around the world and throughout time have modified their bodies, willingly or under coercion, in order to achieve a culturally desirable aesthetic. With her body as central to her role, status, and identity, females manipulate their bodies or their bodies are manipulated for them. In some cases, the body modification is an overt sign of patriarchy, because it enables greater control over the woman's life. This is especially
Faith and Reason Paper Introduction Faith starts in the mind and moves to the will. Aquinas is one of the most well-known scholastics to make that argument.[footnoteRef:2] The mind must consent to the truths of the faith and the heart and mind must then act in unison to bear that faith out in one’s life. This is why the scholastics argued that faith rested on reason—for people are rational beings and need
The final two arguments aim at establishing whether suicide can even be considered as the rational solution. The avoidance of harm refers to the commonly accepted view that hurting oneself is irrational because life is the most precious possession we own. Nonetheless, this argument seems to weaken if we consider the fact that in case of terminal illnesses, suicide can become harm-avoiding since it ends the pain and humiliation which
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now