Verified Document

Philippa Foot Term Paper

Foot: Moral Beliefs L. Jones

Philippa Foot's Moral Beliefs

The concept of moral relativism is extremely troubling for many. Indeed, the human animal is desperately in need of a certain "moral order," or an intense longing to have life's issues, events and decisions neatly classified into realms of "good" and "bad," "right" and wrong. However, as most individuals blessed with a life that stretches into adulthood know all too well, other's conceptions of good and bad actions often differ greatly from one's own -- and, even more puzzling, those "others" seem to genuinely believe in their own conception of reality just as much an individual how holds the completly opposite view. In her work Moral Beliefs, Philippa Foot gives her take on this issue; namely in her response to the viability of systems of belief that allow moral eccentrism (the foundation on which moral relativism is built), and her belief in the untenability of the non-cognitivist position.

From the beginning of her work, Philippa Foot sets out to "look critically at the premises" on which many people reject naturalism -- that values of morality or goodness arise out of the human's inherent understanding of reality, quite apart from special circumstances. In short, it is a philosophy that is the opposite of moral relativism. It is a system on which any individual is equally bound by its moral principles, regardless of evidential facts She writes:

..the whole of moral philosophy, as it is now widely taught, rests on a contrast between statementst of fact and evaluations, which runs something like this: 'The truth or falsity of statements of fact is shown by means of evidence; and what counts as evidence is laid down in the meaning of the expressions occurring in the statement of fact. (83)

The difference, according to Foot, between these evidential principles of fact, and evaluations is significant. She notes that, "...no two people can make the same statement and count completely different things as evidence; in the end one at least of them could be convicted of linguistic ignorance."(83) Further, unlike in the relativist scheme of things, "..."if a man is given good evidence for a factual conclusion he cannot just refute to accept the conclusion on the ground that in his scheme of things this evidence is not evidence at all."(83) To allow oneself to delve into an evaluation of the evidence is to possibly fall into the realm of "moral eccentrism," the unacceptable spawn of non-cognitivism. Again, she writes:

An evaluation is not connected logically with the factual statements on which it is based. One may say that a thing is good because of some fact about I, and another may refuse to take that fact as any evidence at all, for nothing is laid down in the meaning of 'good' which connects it with one piece of 'evidence' rather than another. It follows that a moral eccentric could argue to moral conclusions from quite idiosyncratic premises... (84)

If, for example, one is allowed to accept a non-naturalist point-of-view, then, not only does one run the risk of sinking into abject relativism (the ultimate free-for-all of society). For, not only can an individual who accepts this kind of thinking base his or her moral beliefs on assumptions that only he or she recognize as valid. Further, he or she could also refuse to agree with someone else's evaluation because the assumptions or standards of evaluation are not ones that he or she accepts.

However, according to Foot, this kind of non-naturalism or non-cognitivism is in error, illustrated by the notion that the proper use of words demonstrates their ability to communicate clear evaluations of moral significance and meaning. In specific, Foot illustrates this point in her discussion of the words "proud" and "dangerous."

In specific, Foot explains, in the case of "pride":

Given any description of an object, action, personal characteristic,...

Before we can do so we need to know what would be said about it by the man who is to be proud of it, or feels proud of it; but if he does not hold the right beliefs about it then whatever his attitude is it is not pride.(86)
Hence, the moral, or value assigned to the "pride" in question is directly related to the facts, or "special background" associated with the object in relation to the use of the word. In other words, one could not be "proud" of simply standing up, unless, perhaps, a special circumstance (an injury, for example), made standing up an event worthy of pride.

Of course, Foot's greatest example against non-cognitivism and its descent into moral eccentrism (again the essence of moral relativism), is her discussion of "injury" and its nature as being "bad." Here, the question arises of whether the concept of an injury being "bad" makes sense evidentially.

Specifically, in response to this question, Foot explains that injuries are defined as causing damage and "malfunction" of a part of one's anatomy, that this damage and ensuing malfunction is harmful to the body (and, by extension, to the individual), and that, it is a truth that humans want to prevent harm to their bodies as much a possible.

Therefore, not only is it "right" to prevent injury, but that injury is necessarily "bad."

Further, one can go back to the two terms Foot uses in her explanation, "proud" and "dangerous," to illustrate that this "badness" is connected to the concept of moral virtues in the terms "good" or "harm." She writes, "It is surely clear that moral virtues must be connected with human good or harm, and that it is quite impossible to call anything you like good or harm."(91) Therefore, these kinds of terms illustrate that there is inherent and unrelative meaning in moral terms.

In addition to the established meaning derived from their commonly understood use, Foot also explains that all of these words have an internal judgment placed on them, or an assessment of their "value" good or bad, based on their internal relationship to an "object." Further, it is the connection between the value, the object, and the logical reason that allow one to make the correct (and not relative) judgment concerning that value. Foot specifically makes the leap from the more mundane life value judgments represented by fear, danger, pride, etc., to "those attitudes or beliefs which are the moral philosopher's study."(91) In specific, she writes, "Now we must consider whether those attitudes or beliefs...are similar, or whether such things as 'evaluation' and 'thinking something good' and 'commendation' could logically be found in combination with any object whatsoever."(92) Further, she introduces this consideration with the provision that no "special background" may be introduced. She writes:

We are bound by the terms of our question to refrain from adding any special background, and it should be stated once more that the badness of a man or an action, and not what could be, or be thought, good or bad with a special background. I believe that the view that I am attacking only seems plausible because the special background is surreptitiously introduced. (92)

Here, in the realm of the moral virtue, it is not enough to understand or accept the value of a moral belief simply based on the "use" of the words or terms. Instead, a sense of background must be introduced, allowing a cognitive approach. Take, for example, Foot's explanation of the understanding of the moral belief, "This is a good action." On this sentence, Foot notes that it is not enough to understand the sentence on its own, for example, as one would with the term "it is dangerous." Instead, one must know exactly "how" it is a good action. Is it a brave action, a selfless action, a wise action? In order to understand the goodness of the situation, one must have awareness,…

Cite this Document:
Copy Bibliography Citation

Related Documents

Philippa Foot Though Experiment for Mill and Kant
Words: 1370 Length: 5 Document Type: Essay

Philippa Foot Thought Experiment 1 J.S. Mill would tell the rescuer in Rescue I to save the five as that would promote the greatest common good. In Rescue II, it is not as easy to say the same thing—for while it is obviously better to save five than it is to save one, intentionally killing one to save five does not come with the same moral assurances as simply choosing to save

Active and Passive Euthanasia. Why Does James
Words: 1642 Length: 4 Document Type: Essay

active and passive euthanasia. Why does James Rachels think there is no moral difference between them? Active euthanasia is the "mercy killing" of a life to prevent further suffering; passive euthanasia is deliberately allowing that life to die of "natural" causes. James Rachels believes there is no moral difference between active and passive euthanasia for a few reasons. First, in many cases where passive euthanasia is allowed (meaning it has

Euthanasia It Is Generally Believed
Words: 905 Length: 2 Document Type: Term Paper

This can ultimately become the justification for refusal to euthanize a person even if they have given their permission. While the rights of the individual must be respected, even if they wish to die, others cannot, must not, accede to the individuals' wishes if they do not agree with it. The underlying basis of euthanasia must be the ending of a life who's continuance is generally accepted as an

Women's Body Image
Words: 2056 Length: 6 Document Type: Research Paper

Female Body Women around the world and throughout time have modified their bodies, willingly or under coercion, in order to achieve a culturally desirable aesthetic. With her body as central to her role, status, and identity, females manipulate their bodies or their bodies are manipulated for them. In some cases, the body modification is an overt sign of patriarchy, because it enables greater control over the woman's life. This is especially

The Relationship of Reason to Faith
Words: 3649 Length: 12 Document Type: Research Paper

Faith and Reason Paper Introduction Faith starts in the mind and moves to the will. Aquinas is one of the most well-known scholastics to make that argument.[footnoteRef:2] The mind must consent to the truths of the faith and the heart and mind must then act in unison to bear that faith out in one’s life. This is why the scholastics argued that faith rested on reason—for people are rational beings and need

Deontological Response to Euthanasia Has
Words: 1426 Length: 4 Document Type: Thesis

The final two arguments aim at establishing whether suicide can even be considered as the rational solution. The avoidance of harm refers to the commonly accepted view that hurting oneself is irrational because life is the most precious possession we own. Nonetheless, this argument seems to weaken if we consider the fact that in case of terminal illnesses, suicide can become harm-avoiding since it ends the pain and humiliation which

Sign Up for Unlimited Study Help

Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.

Get Started Now