Verified Document

Harts Postscript Dworkin's Early Work Essay

Both of these perspectives are, from Hart's perspective, too extreme: he wants a legal theory which would be free from moral evaluations or moral commitments (unlike Finnis' approach), while remaining a descriptive theory of the practice rather than a participation in it (unlike Dworkin's approach). Hart was trying to keep a difficult middle position (Hacker, 1977-page 31). He argued that a legal theory should be constructed around the perspective of someone who accepted the legal system, but the theory itself (or, to put the matter differently, the theorist herself) need not, and should not, endorse the system (as one which is generally just or which creates binding moral obligations). In other words, the theory simultaneously: (1) attempts to take into account the participant's perspective; and (2) manages to choose among possible participants' perspectives without having to make moral judgments; while

(3) keeping sufficient distance from the participants' perspective to allow for moral criticism of the whole system / enterprise (Perry, 1995-page 52).

The danger is of Hart's position sliding towards an Austin-like command theory, on one side, and a position closer to Finnis' or Dworkin's, on the other (Hacker, 1977-page 14). To put the matter a different way, the question is how to take seriously the need to accept the perspective of a participant in a practice while still maintaining a sufficient distance to be able to criticise the practice (and the participants) (Raz, 1979-page 17). In social theory (or perhaps, more accurately, "social sciences meta-theory"), this has led to an ongoing debate regarding whether an attempt to "explain each culture or society in its own terms ... rules out an account which shows them up as wrong, confused or deluded" (Ball, 1990-page 72). (One can say: if you claim to understand the perspective of the believing participant of a particular practice, but you think the practice is irrational and cruel, then you have not really understood or properly incorporated the perspective of the believer, because that is not how it looks to him or her (Twining, 1979-page 34). An additional complication, one whose implications are hard to tease out, is that in the social sciences one must consider the role of an internal point-of-view, both in the evaluation of data gathered and in the actual gathering of that data nor to evaluating it. This additional point is unclear in its implications because it ties into the debate on what it would mean to "gather evidence" (Cohen, 1984-page 18) for a general theory of law (and what kind of evidence one would want).

Conclusion

Hart offers a contrast between possible types of legal theory, a contrast based on images. One type of theory is to be used "within" the legal system: for example, in telling a judge how to decide disputes. Another type of theory involves looking at the system "from the outside." Basing the argument on the images, one would say that a theory cannot be simultaneously part of the legal system and a description of the system from the outside. In some ways, this last argument is a strange one for Hart to have put forward, for one of the most significant aspects of Hart's approach to law was that it demanded that we look at the perspectives of citizens and officials within a legal system, the "internal point-of-view," in constructing a theory of law.

The main question for this exchange between Dworkin and Hart is how much we can rely on the images, on the metaphors, alone in evaluating or creating arguments. It does sound strange to say that a theory is simultaneously part of the system and the best explanation of the system. However, this type of argument, with all its hints of circularity, is actually relatively common in modern philosophy; examples include the hermeneutic circle in literary theory, and John Rawls' use of reflective equilibrium in moral and political theory.

To the extent that there is a true conflict between Dworkin and Hart, it is at those times when Dworkin states or implies that there is no room for a substantive, detailed and interesting descriptive theory of law (that is not interpretative). This struggle can be seen not only in Hart's insistence on the space for and need for a (non? interpretative) descriptive theory of law in general, but also in his disagreement with any attempt to recast legal positivism as being about justifying present or future coercion,...

Hart ed., London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1955).
Austin, Regina, "Sapphire Bound! (Minority Feminist Scholarship)" (1989) Wisconsin Law Review 539.

Baird, Douglas; Gertner, Robert and Picker, Randal, Game Theory and the Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994).

Baker, Gordon, "Defeasibility and Meaning" in Law, Morality, and Society (P M.S. Hacker and J. Raz eds., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 26-57.

Balkin, Jack, "Transcendental Deconstruction, Transcendent Justice" (1994) 92 Michigan Law Review 1131.

Ball, Milner, "The Legal Academy and Minority Scholars" (1990) 103 Harvard Law Review 1855.

Cohen, M. ed., Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence (London: Duckworth 1984)

Dworkin, Gerald ed., Morality, Harm and the Law (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1994).

Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986).

Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977).

Eekelaar, J.M., "Principles of Revolutionary Legality" in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Second Series (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), pp. 22-43.

Epstein, Richard, "A Theory of Strict Liability" (1973) 2 Journal of Legal Studies 151.

Eskridge, William, "Gaylegal Narratives" (1994) 46 Stanford Law Review 607.

Hart, H.L.A., "Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence" (1954) 70 Law Quarterly Review 37-60, reprinted in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 21-48.

Hacker, P.M.S., "Hart's Philosophy of Law" in Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart (P M.S. Hacker and J. Raz eds., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 1-25.

Hacker, P.M.S. And Raz, Joseph eds., Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977).

Mackie, John, "The Third Theory of Law" (1977) 7 Philosophy and Public Affairs 3, reprinted in Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence (M. Cohen ed., London: Duckworth, 1984), pp. 161-170.

MacCormick, Neil, H.L.A. Hart. Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).

Perry, Stephen, "Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory" in Law and Interpretation (A. Marmor ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 97-135.

Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979).

Twining, William, "Academic Law and Legal Philosophy: The Significance of Herbert Hart" (1979) 95 Law Quarterly Review 557.

Twining, William, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement (Norman, Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press, 1985).

Tushnet, Mark, "Following the Rules Laid Down: A Critique of Interpretation and Neutral Principles" (1983) 96 Harvard Law Review 781.

Twining, William, "Academic Law and Legal Philosophy: The Significance of Herbert Hart" (1979) 95 Law Quarterly Review 557.

Weber, Max, The Methodology of the Social Sciences (E. Shils and H. Finch eds., New York: Free Press, 1949).

Weber, Max, "Objectivity' in Social Science and Social Policy" in The Methodology of the Social Sciences (E. Shils and H. Finch eds., New York: Free Press, 1949), pp. 50-112.

Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), pp. 95-96.

See Hart, The Concept of Law, pp. 54-57, 79-88.

The foundational work advocating a hermeneutic approach to social theory is probably Max Weber, "Objectivity' in Social Science and Social Policy" in The Methodology of the Social Sciences (E. Shils and H. Finch eds., New York: Free Press, 1949), pp. 50-112, Hart's immediate influence (and a source almost as important as Weber on this topic) was Winch, The Idea of a Social Science; see Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 242.

William Twining, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement (Norman, Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press, 1985), pp. 10-11.

HL.A. Hart, "Introduction" in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford:…

Sources used in this document:
Works Cited

Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (H L.A. Hart ed., London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1955).

Austin, Regina, "Sapphire Bound! (Minority Feminist Scholarship)" (1989) Wisconsin Law Review 539.

Baird, Douglas; Gertner, Robert and Picker, Randal, Game Theory and the Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994).

Baker, Gordon, "Defeasibility and Meaning" in Law, Morality, and Society (P M.S. Hacker and J. Raz eds., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 26-57.
Cite this Document:
Copy Bibliography Citation

Related Documents

Jurisprudence As a Theory in Law, Jurisprudence
Words: 2009 Length: 7 Document Type: Term Paper

Jurisprudence As a theory in law, Jurisprudence involves varying philosophical perceptions about the purposes of law, the legal system and the institutions developed to regulate law. In an effort to understand the basic, fundamental reasoning for law and of legal systems, legal scholars have developed theoretical frameworks within the umbra of jurisprudence. For the purposes of this paper, jurisprudential philosophies will include natural law, legal positivism and constructivist theories of law. Aristotle,

Imam Al-Shafi'i in Islamic Jurisprudence
Words: 1735 Length: 6 Document Type: Term Paper

but, according to all other fuqah?', it should be transferred to the public treasury, because it belongs to the Muslims. According to Sh-fi ), the Muslims inherit it on the grounds of their being members of the same group (alta s-b); Ab? Han-fa agrees, on the basis of one of the two traditions reported by him (which includes Sh-fi's opinion), although the other tradition grounds it on friendship (muw-l-t), not

Workplace Discrimination Jurisprudence in Workplace
Words: 2256 Length: 8 Document Type: Research Proposal

Johnson v Transportation Agency (1986) The two above cases both resulted in a broadening of the scopes and protections of the Civil Rights Act via jurisprudence. In Johnson v Transportation Agency (1986), a very different result was reached that shows the changing nature and understanding of discrimination and how it work in society. The difference in this case is also directly and explicitly related to the differences in the original plaintiffs

Obtaining a Degree in Jurisprudence
Words: 497 Length: 2 Document Type: Term Paper

Upon becoming a paralegal, I may then begin to make use of the administrative and organizational skills I already possess to enhance my knowledge of the law. Further, other than my many years of experience in administrative positions, I have the advantage of many years in the military in general. Essentially, the law is a vast set of rules to be applied evenly and fairly across varying cultures. The military

Dworkin Jurisprudence
Words: 648 Length: 2 Document Type: Term Paper

Dworkin Jurisprudence The rule of law entails the practical manifestation of our social and philosophical ideals: the rule of law is ideals in action. The rule of law allows public standards to be applied to personal behaviors. The rule of law also requires the proper exercise of power by a governing body. The government enforces the law, but no individual is above the law. The principles of law include the following. The

Feminist Jurisprudence: Landmark Decisions Relating
Words: 1723 Length: 5 Document Type: Term Paper

One criticism is that the corporate and business world is more concerned with self-interest rather then ethics and human rights. "Corporate America, upon which much of the burden of economic growth depends, does what is good for itself. Such self-interest has had the effect of barring women from most executive suites and maintaining status quo gender roles...." (Gibelman, 2003. p 22) This is an aspect which, in combination with

Sign Up for Unlimited Study Help

Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.

Get Started Now