Racism and Business Ethics
Despite a myriad of laws outlawing discrimination and protecting civil rights, racism continues to pervade all aspects of American business.
This can be seen in the pay disparity between the races, the ongoing discrimination against black men seeking employment and lack of racial minorities in upper management and other decision-making positions in industry.
This paper uses the utilitarian and value judgment theories to examine the ethical nature of racism in business. The first part of the paper evaluates how these two ethical traditions would view racism. In the second part, the paper looks at the various methods for addressing racism in American business, focusing on diversity training and affirmative action. It then evaluates the rightness of these programs, both from a utilitarian and a values-based ethics.
In the conclusion, the paper argues for a combination of diversity training and goals-oriented affirmative action as an ethical way to address the pervasive problem of racism in American businesses.
Racism and "values" ethics
Aristotle's value-based ethics is premised on a system that allows human happiness. Aristotle believed that happiness is based on human nature. The nature of happiness is itself based on human nature. For Aristotle, happiness can only spring from the rational part of the human soul and is therefore a goal unique to humans (Grant 1989).
Aristotle believes that every person actively pursues happiness. However, he also believed that true happiness could only lie in realizing the intellectual needs of the rational or human elements of the soul.
On a larger scale, the pursuit of individual happiness through an intellectual life contributes to a civilized and ethical society as a whole. In fact, happiness is impossible outside the state, since humans are political and social animals (Grant 1989). Happiness is thus something to be continually strived for, through the active life of a rational and virtuous human being.
For Aristotle, true happiness only derives from a person's virtue which he defines a person's excellence in fulfilling a particular function. Thus, a "happy" person is active in accordance with his or her best virtue (Grant 1989). In this moral state, an individual is able to perform his or her proper function well.
In this light, racism emerges as incompatible with Aristotle's value-based ethics. Through the lens of racism, a person is evaluated not according to his or her best virtue. Instead, a person is judged according to the false value of skin color.
Such an action is not moral because it causes harm on two levels. First, since an individual could only achieve happiness through fulfilling their virtue, racism serves as a significant obstacle to individual human happiness.
In addition, Aristotle recognized that humans are social animals, who derive happiness from pursuing values not just for themselves but for their family and community as well. In Aristotelian values ethics, racism prevents individuals from enacting their best virtues.
This denies them the opportunity to contribute their virtue to the greater community as well.
Utilitarianism and racism
In the second chapter of Utilitarianism, philosopher John Stuart Mill (1987) wrote, "Actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness; wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness." Following his predecessors, such as David Hume and Jeremy Bentham, Mill referred to formulation as the principle of utility
Upon first reading, the converse Mill's principle of utility is that actions which do not produce happiness for the greatest number is wrong. However, this is a simplistic reading of Mill's formulation because Mill placed a greater premium on the effects of one's action. If an action produces more beneficial effects than harmful ones, then according to the principle of utility, the action is right. When the amount of harmful effects exceeds the beneficial ones, then an action is wrong (Mill 1987).
In the second chapter of Utilitarianism, Mill explained how the principle of utility should prioritize the results or consequences of an action over the motives of the actor or agent. This formulation refutes most of the classical theories on morality that preceded Mill. According to utilitarian philosophy, a person may appear morally good because he or she acts based on good intentions. However, the action is separate from the worth of the actor or agent. Thus, a morally good person may still be capable of actions that cause others a great deal of harm (Mill 1987). Mill's utilitarian philosophy would thus judge this person's actions as wrong despite the agent's good motives.
Mill's formulation provides a useful basis for evaluating the morality of racism, both in general and in the American business world.
Clearly, any supposed benefits of racism are outweighed by its harmful individual and social effects.
Thus, according to utilitarian principles, people who sought to continue racist practices such as a segregated workplace may have had legitimate...
E. The voices who argue that America should and could be an imperial superpower, but lacks sound practical judgment. The thesis of this paper is that the history of the Roman Empire can be matched to that of the United States in terms of economy, political power, as well as aspirations. In this sense, present day America is very similar to fourth of even fifth century Rome; this poses one stringent
In this regard, Meyers concludes that, "As for Flory, environment has been too much for him, for he is not really alcoholic or crapulous by nature, and he regrets it when a girl from England arrives to stay at Kyauktada; she is a poverty-stricken little snob on the look-out for a husband, but he has not seen a spinster for a decade, and he succumbs on the spot whereupon
Our semester plans gives you unlimited, unrestricted access to our entire library of resources —writing tools, guides, example essays, tutorials, class notes, and more.
Get Started Now